- From: Drew McDermott <drew.mcdermott@yale.edu>
- Date: Wed, 3 Dec 2003 14:00:48 -0500 (EST)
- To: www-rdf-rules@w3.org
[me] >The NAF approach is likely to be much more efficient, much easier to >implement, and much more likely to yield a useful conclusion than the >heavy-duty theorem prover. [Pat Hayes] All true. It is also likely to be wrong, unfortunately. The fact that you can't think of a closer airport doesn't usually qualify as a good reason to conclude that there isn't one, unless you also know for sure that you know all the airport locations, so that if you don't know it, then its not there. Like, for example, if you have a list of all the airports. If you make this explicit, as you should, then you are back doing 'heavy-duty' reasoning. I was trying to stay within the vocabulary of the example, and I was assuming a plausible context that I didn't state, namely that someone was planning a trip. If you replace "nearest airport" by "nearest airport reasonable to travel someplace from here," then negation as failure is a reasonable strategy, assuming you know all the airports in the vicinity. BTW, calling it 'heavy-duty' is misleading. In the first case you have made all the equality reasoning explicit. In a prolog-style implementation this is all buried in the backtracking done by the interpreter: but it still needs to be done. The same actual *reasoning* is involved in both cases. Yes. But the NAF version is stylized in a way that permits efficient implementation. If you could be sure that the alternative always involved iterating through a list and doing a set of equality substitutions, you could probably find an equally efficient implementation. (I've often wondered why no one has worked on this.) In the general case, though, you have to have a system that does general-purpose reasoning about equality, which can involve a lot of search. > I hope the people who deprecate it realize >that the heavy-duty theorem prover is the only alternative. Its not a matter of alternatives. If you want to draw checkable valid conclusions, then you need to do this kind of reasoning. I don't want to draw checkable valid conclusions. If you want to make random guesses and hope for the best then you can of course work faster, but don't expect others to believe in your conclusions. At least I'll _have_ conclusions. Negation-as-failure is NOT a good general reasoning strategy: 99.99% of the time it will immediately produce childishly ludicrous conclusions: I don't know anyone called Jose, so there isn't anyone called Jose; I never heard of SARS, ... Where have you been? Of course negation-as-failure is not the way to handle "not" in general; it's the way to handle it when you don't care about possible nearby secret airports and the like. The industrial uses of Prolog-style rules all are designed within controlled environments, typically using databases, where such special conditions can be assumed. To repeat what I said above, if you use NAF as an efficient way to draw valid conclusions, you're right. I prefer to think of it as a way to draw conclusions that may well be wrong, in situations where the wrongness of a probably correct conclusion is not fatal. The burden is on someone who finds this distasteful to show that pure deductive techniques will suffice for real-world applications. -- Drew -- -- Drew McDermott Yale University CS Dept.
Received on Wednesday, 3 December 2003 14:01:04 UTC