- From: ingvar_johansson <ingvar.johansson@philos.umu.se>
- Date: Fri, 4 Sep 2009 17:40:40 +0200 (CEST)
- To: "[ontolog-forum]" <ontolog-forum@ontolog.cim3.net>
- Cc: "[ontolog-forum]" <ontolog-forum@ontolog.cim3.net>, "semantic-web@w3.org" <semantic-web@w3.org>
Gary Berg-Cross wrote: > We may think that science uses a form of nominalism as we formulate > theories whose simplifications name concepts used in the theory that may > be useful for the theory, but not reflect the deep reality. An oft cited > one is the use of species in Biology. Ernst Mayr argued against a simple > "typological thinking," found in biology (even evolutionary biology). > Belief in the reality of "species" as a general form is a type of > Platonic idealism, but in practice its use in theory seems to be just a > nominalist use. The history about Mayr is a bit more complicated. Below you can find two pages from the book I. Johansson (me) and N. Lynoe, "Medicine & Philosophy. A Twenty-Frist Century Introduction" (ontos 2008, pp. 418-20) --------- How then to characterize what is common to all species, or at least to sexual species? /---/ Evolutionary biology has made another kind of move; it has dropped the pure class concept of species (Ghiselin 1997). A common modern definition of sexual species, propounded by the German ornithologist and philosopher of biology Ernst Mayr (1904-2005), says: • Biological species are groups of actually or potentially interbreeding natural populations, which are reproductively isolated from other such groups. The philosophical change involved in the move from the *typological* species concept to the *biological* species concept is indicated by the term ‘population’. According to the typological concept, a species is a class, and a class has no boundaries in space and/or time. But a population has such boundaries, and more than that. A population is not just a class plus a conventional spatial and/or temporal boundary; the individuals in the population should also be linked by chains of interaction, which makes the population into a kind of spatiotemporal particular. In a sense, the individuals of a population are to the population what the cells of an organism are to the organism. A population is, just like an organism, not a repeatable and class but a particular and a property-bearer. The individual plants or animals of a biological species are not *members* but *parts* of their species. In-between the individuals and the whole population, biologists sometimes discern other kinds of parts, e.g., local populations or ‘demes’. A thought experiment may highlight the essence of the biological species concept. If, on another planet (P) somewhere in the Universe, there are lion-like animals that in principle can produce fertile offspring together with Earth-lions, these P-lions are nonetheless parts of another population. Therefore, according to the definition of biological species, Earth-lions and P-lions have to be regarded as two different biological species. Mayr is quite explicit on this (1988, p. 343). And a similar remark holds for the temporal dimension. If, on Earth, lions become extinct someday, but are then produced a second time by natural selection, then these second-time lions would be a different population and, therefore, also a distinct biological species. The expression ‘reproductively isolated’ is given such a broad sense in Mayr’s definition that not only fertilization barriers (no zygote can be formed), hybrid barriers (the zygote is not viable), and hybrid sterility count as examples of reproductive isolation, but so also do behavioral differences (the courtship rituals do not fit those of their mating partner) and significant physical barriers (oceans, galaxies, etc.). Typological species (species-as-classes-and-repeatables) are by definition unchangeable, whereas biological species (species-as-populations-and-particulars) allow change, since they are property-bearers, too. Biological species can move on Earth, they can exchange one niche for another, and they can even radically change their genetic material. Does this new species concept therefore make the old typological concept obsolete in the way modern chemistry has made obsolete the concept of phlogiston? In other words: does the old typological species concept refer to something merely fictional? The answer is straightforwardly ‘no, it does not’. For the notion of ‘potential reproduction’, which is at the heart of the typological species concept, is still as applicable to individuals of different sexes as it ever was, and it is even used in Mayr’s definition. In all probability, the typological species concept will always be useful in some restricted contexts. It might even be very useful within central biology. If it is true that speciation only occurs during some relatively brief periods of time (the theory of punctuated equilibria), the typological species concept is as applicable in the normal equilibrium periods as it was in pre-Darwinian theorizing. On the other hand, it is not only evolutionary biology with its theory of vertical gene transfer that has made it hard to apply the typological species concept everywhere. Some organisms with prokaryote cells (e.g., bacteria) and some unicellular eukaryotes show evidence of horizontal gene transfer, i.e., some organisms seem to receive genetic material not only from their ancestors. When an organism produces an offspring and there is a non-negligible horizontal gene transfer, then the organism cannot be said to reproduce itself. Genetic engineering is a form of artificial horizontal gene transfer. (The move from species-as-repeatables to species-as-particulars is retained in phylogenetic systematics, the discipline that devotes itself exclusively to finding genealogical trees that mirror the process of speciation on Earth.) --------------------- Best, Ingvar -- home page: http://hem.passagen.se/ijohansson/index.html
Received on Monday, 7 September 2009 11:28:56 UTC