- From: Ogbuji, Chimezie <OGBUJIC@ccf.org>
- Date: Thu, 26 Jun 2008 18:31:07 -0400
- To: "Pat Hayes" <phayes@ihmc.us>
- cc: "Adrian Walker" <adriandwalker@gmail.com>, "[ontolog-forum]" <ontolog-forum@ontolog.cim3.net>, "John F. Sowa" <sowa@bestweb.net>, welty@watson.ibm.com, semantic_web@googlegroups.com, "public-semweb-lifesci hcls" <public-semweb-lifesci@w3.org>, semanticweb@yahoogroups.com
Hey, Pat. Comments below > I would disagree about this case being the exception. >Negation as failure can be validly used to infer from a >failure if the data is controlled (which is especially the >case with well-designed experiments where it would be >irresponsible to to do otherwise). > > >What are you referring to by "well-designed experiments"? "Well-designed experiments" is probably not a useful characterization, so let me try again. Let's say you are nurse performing a history and physical assesment on a patient in order to make entries into his/her medical record and one of the questions you ask *routinely* is whether or not the patient has a particular symptom/problem: headaches for instance. If the patient says: "no", and you are conforming to default negation as part of a subsequent analysis, then it would seem sufficient to not make any assertion about the existence of a headache. Otherwise, you would need to be able to either infer that the patient doesn't have a headache (provably false) *or* have an explicit assertion of absence: I. _:a a cpr:patient II. _:a a cpr:patient _:a a cpr:PersonWithoutHeadache My point is that, in the first model you *can* infer that the patient doesn't have a headache because the assertion is missing and you *know* that the question was asked. The assumption that knowledge is *always* incomplete seems (to me) to not account for situations where the data is indeed complete specifically because the process of collecting it is controlled. >OK, but that does not ensure that if P is not asserted, then >it is known to be false. In fact, rather the opposite. But it does ensure this - precisely as part of the requirements at the point where the data is collected. My general point is that where you have decent control over the quality of the data in general or at least in the process of how it is populated, default negation can be a useful tool for allowing a person doing analysis to make (safe) assumptions from the absence of data. >You can make such inferences validly only when you have some >reason to suppose that if the proposition were true, the >content would not be missing. Right, the reason in this case would be knowledge of the expectations of how the data is collected. >I don't mean to deny that such >circumstances do exist, in some cases with an explicit warrant >for the entailment, but they are certainly not the usual case. >The usual case is that your knowledge is incomplete. Our >knowledge of almost everything is incomplete. Certainly, but I'm simply pushing back (slightly) on what often is the typical argument against non-monotonic inference: the claim that knowledge is *always* incomplete regardless of how you come about it. > without the burden of classic negation, which requires >a significant amount of effort >Nonsense. There is no 'burden' of classical negation. Negation >IS classical negation. If you conclude that P is false, and >express this using a negation connective, you are using >classical negation. (If your *conclusion* from a failure to >prove P is that P is not proven, then your reasoning is >completely classical also; but then you are only concluding >failure, not negation from failure.) The burden I was refering to, is the difference between the simple (and controlled) absence of assertions and needing to either conclude that the assertion is false (via inference) or having to express it explicitely (i.e. I. versus II. From the above example with the patient and his/her headache). Note, I'm pushing back slightly on what often seems like unadulturated dogma, not trying to be dogmatic myself :) (either having a large amounts of assertions about >class disjointedness, etc. or requiring explicit assertions >about the absence of data) > > >You have to say what is true in order to draw reliable >conclusions from it. Or, alternatively, you control the process of how the data is populated in order to draw (simple) conclusions that don't require significant inference. No? >This can be done in tedious ways or, with >the right notations and conventions, more compactly. You are >reacting against some of the more tedious notational results >of using simple textbook logics. But if you want to be able to >infer, from the fact that something is in a class A, that it >is not in another class B, then you must have some way to know >that A and B are disjoint. Because if they aren't, that >conclusion is not valid. No amount of grumbling about >classical negation is going to get over that basic fact. I'm not grumbling about it, I'm just trying to demonstrate that there are situations where default negation (by itself) is a responsible means to conclude the absence of some assertion. > to ensure that you can prove that P is false. >You have to know somehow. You might just know because someone >told you, > or because you know that if it were true then you >would have it recorded, and you don't. But you have to know >this. Of course, I'm suggesting that there are valid, controlled scenarios where you *do* know this. Chimezie (chee-meh) Ogbuji Lead Systems Analyst Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery Cleveland Clinic Foundation 9500 Euclid Avenue/ W26 Cleveland, Ohio 44195 Office: (216)444-8593 ogbujic@ccf.org P Please consider the environment before printing this e-mail Cleveland Clinic is ranked one of the top hospitals in America by U.S. News & World Report (2007). Visit us online at http://www.clevelandclinic.org for a complete listing of our services, staff and locations. Confidentiality Note: This message is intended for use only by the individual or entity to which it is addressed and may contain information that is privileged, confidential, and exempt from disclosure under applicable law. If the reader of this message is not the intended recipient or the employee or agent responsible for delivering the message to the intended recipient, you are hereby notified that any dissemination, distribution or copying of this communication is strictly prohibited. If you have received this communication in error, please contact the sender immediately and destroy the material in its entirety, whether electronic or hard copy. Thank you.
Received on Thursday, 26 June 2008 22:32:04 UTC